Zeno of Sidon
Phoenician Encyclopedia
Click for Mobile Version
    Ban Wikipedia   en.wikipedia is is a non-peer-reviewed website
with agenda and is anti-Lebanese & anti-Semitic 
Highlight any text; our page(s) will read it. Text to speech


Translate

Born c. 150 BC in Sidon, Phoenicia and died in Athens, Greece c. 70 BC.

      Twitter Logo Join PhoeniciaOrg Twitter
for alerts on new articles
Facebook Logo Visit our Facebook Page
for additional, new studies

To understand the philosophy of Zeno one needs to make some comments about the philosopher Epicurus who founded the Epicurean School to which Zeno later belonged. Epicurus, who lived from 341 BC to 270 BC, founded his own School of philosophy based on his teachings. These teachings were designed to indicate a means of living ones life, and they aimed both to guarantee happiness and to provide a means to find it. Epicurus had no interest in science for its own sake and he was a severe critic of mathematics. On science he wrote:

If we were not troubled by our suspicions of the phenomena of the sky and about death, and also by our failure to grasp the limits of pain and desires, we should have no need of natural science.

His criticisms of mathematics were very superficial of little importance since he clearly had very little understanding of the subject. In 306 BC he founded his School in Athens in the garden of his house. Reasonably enough the School became known as The Garden.

Apollodorus, the writer of more than 400 books, was a prominent follower of Epicurus who lived in the 2nd century BC. Zeno of Sidon was a student of Apollodorus and he studied, and later taught, in the Garden in Athens. Cicero heard him teaching there in 79 BC.

Zeno was a man of great learning who wrote on a very wide range of topics. It is believed that, among the areas he studied, he contributed to logic, atomic theory, biology, ethics, literary style, oratory, poetry, the theory of knowledge, and to mathematics. Except for the last mentioned two topics, one knows very little about the contributions that he made. Here is a discussion of the only two areas to which Zeno contributed and where details of his contributions are quite well known, namely the theory of knowledge and to mathematics.

Although Epicurus, the founder of the School to which Zeno belonged, had no real mathematical abilities and criticized the subject from a position of ignorance, this is far from true of Zeno who had a deep understanding of the subject. Zeno made deep criticisms of the axioms that Euclid set out in The Elements. For example he claimed that Euclid's first proposition assumes that two straight lines can intersect in at most one point but Euclid does not have this as an axiom, nor can it be deduced from the other axioms.

Zeno also attacked Euclid's proof of the equality of right angles on the grounds that it presupposes the existence of a right angle. Proclus also says that an Epicurean (almost certainly Zeno but Proclus does not name him) claimed that Euclid assumes that every curve is infinitely divisible, but again this cannot be deduced from the axioms.

Some modern authors have suggested that these claims give Zeno of Sidon some justification to be considered as having been the first person to consider the possibility of non-Euclidean geometry. This is a little far fetched particularly since Zeno's aim was certainly not this. Rather his aim was to give substantial arguments against mathematics supporting the anti-mathematical beliefs of Epicurus.

Heath writes regarding comments by Proclus concerning Zeno:

Zeno argued generally that, even if we admit the fundamental principles of geometry, the deductions from them cannot be proved without the admission of something else as well which has not been included in the said principles, and he intended by means of these criticisms to destroy the whole of geometry.

Mathematicians of course, came to the defense of their subject, rather than to try to understand the deep and justified comments of Zeno. As von Fritz writes:

Zeno's criticisms of Euclid are pertinent, however, and if any of the ancient philosophers and mathematicians who tried to refute them had been able to grasp their full implications, the development of mathematics might have taken a different turn.

Many people gain an important position in history, or fail to gain such a position, as a result of luck. Had there been a mathematician following Zeno who could have continued to develop his ideas then one might know Zeno today as a major figure whose flash of mathematical genius changed the course of mathematics. This was not to be, however, and the brilliance of Zeno's ideas was not appreciated for many centuries.

One knows more of Zeno through one of his students Philodemus of Gadara. Now Philodemus studied under Zeno in Athens and then moved to Rome in 75 BC to work for the Roman aristocrat Lucius Calpurnius Piso. Philodemus then went to live in Lucius's villa at Herculaneum, near Naples, taking with him his considerable library of papyri.

When Vesuvius erupted in 79 AD, Herculaneum together with Pompeii and Stabiae, was destroyed. Herculaneum was buried by a compact mass of material about 16 m deep that preserved the city until excavations began in the 18th century. Special conditions of humidity of the ground conserved wood, cloth, food, and in particular Philodemus's papyri.

The papyri contain remarkable information written by Philodemus describing the arguments of his teacher Zeno with the Stoics. Although Zeno's Epicurean philosophy of the desire for pleasure seems the direct opposite of the Stoic's ethic of duty, the consequences on how they lived their lives were quite similar. The arguments described by Philodemus concerned the foundations of knowledge. Von Fritz writes:

In this dispute Zeno defended the old Epicurean doctrine that all human knowledge is derived exclusively from experience. What make it interesting, however, is that he bases his defense on a theory ... that is essentially an anticipation of John Stuart Mill's theory of induction. ... Zeno insisted that all knowledge is fundamentally derived by inference to all cases from a great many cases without observed counter-instance.

Sources:

  1. J J O'Connor and E F Robertson
  2. Biography in Dictionary of Scientific Biography (New York 1970-1990).
  3. G Vlastos, Zeno of Sidon as a Critic of Euclid, in The Classical Tradition : Literary and Historical Studies in Honor of Harry Caplan (New York, 1966), 148-159.
  4. L Adam, Das Wahrheits- und Hypothesen problem bei Demokrit, Epikur und Zeno, dem Epikureer (Göttingen, 1947)
  5. T L Heath, A history of Greek mathematics I, II (Oxford, 1931).
  6. University of St Andrews, Scotland and School of Mathematics and Statistics

 


DISCLAIMER: Opinions expressed in this site do not necessarily represent Phoenicia.org nor do they necessarily reflect those of the various authors, editors, and owner of this site. Consequently, parties mentioned or implied cannot be held liable or responsible for such opinions.

DISCLAIMER TWO:
This is to certify that this website, phoenicia.org is NOT in any way related to, associated with or supports the Phoenician International Research Center, phoeniciancenter.org, the World Lebanese Cultural Union (WLCU) or any other website or organization foreign or domestic. Consequently, any claims of association with this website are null.

 

Additional references, sources and bibliography (Please don't write and ask me for references. You can find them at the end of article or in Bibliography)
Home

Phoenicia, A Bequest Unearthed -- Phoenician Encyclopedia

© Copyright, All rights reserved by holders of original referenced materials and compiler on all pages linked to this site of: https://phoenicia.org © Phoenician Canaanite Encyclopedia -- © Phoenician Encyclopedia -- © Punic Encyclopedia -- © Canaanite Encyclopedia -- © Encyclopedia Phoeniciana, Encyclopedia Punica, Encyclopedia Canaanitica.  

The material in this website was researched, compiled, & designed by Salim George Khalaf as owner, author & editor.
Declared and implied copyright laws must be observed at all time for all text or graphics in compliance with international and domestic legislation.


Contact: Salim George Khalaf, Byzantine Phoenician Descendent
Salim is from Shalim, Phoenician god of dusk, whose place was Urushalim/Jerusalem
"A Bequest Unearthed, Phoenicia" — Encyclopedia Phoeniciana

This site has been online for more than 21 years.
We have more than 420,000 words.
The equivalent of this website is about 2,000 printed pages.

Trade Mark
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20